Hello friends.
We have made it to the endzone of Philosophantasy. See, that’s funny because endzone is football terminology and this blog heavily featured football in the fall semester. For my final installment, I’m going to be doing a semi-extensive breakdown of the implications of Machiavellism. We’re going to talk about a couple of critical nuances in his theory of governance and leadership. If you’ve read this far, I hope you will learn something or maybe even be able to identify a Machiavel in a book you’ve read or a movie you’ve watched. Let’s philosophize, one last time!
Here’s a brief recap of what we know about Machiavelli:
- He was a Florentine diplomat in the 15th century.
- Italy was splintered into many warring city-states, of which Florence was usually the weakest.
- As such, Machiavelli sought to build institutions and systems for governance that could withstand the turmoil and the constant upheaval around him.
- To this end, he disputed the Platonic notion that the best or most effective rulers were the ones who were most virtuous and good, in a moral sense. As such, politics is irreducible to morality.
With all of this, we get the pithy “it is better to be feared than loved” from Machiavelli. In this post, I want to try to figure out whether this maxim is overly reductive. For starters, it seems strange to suggest a ruler should care more about entrenching their authority over legitimacy. If Machiavelli was so bent on avoiding the constant tumult and disruption to authority that typified his era, how could he conscionably endorse a philosophy that accepted the disapproval of the people as a condition of rulership?
Seems counterintuitive at best, and destructive at worst.
Machiavelli has three layers of responses to this admittedly incisive challenge.
Firstly, his theory of effective leadership is situational. Machiavelli does not promote or encourage people to act in morally transgressive ways all the time. He is simply pointing out that there are a wealth of scenarios where winning and maintaining political power is only possible if a leader is readily willing and capable to act outside the moral codes that govern the lives of ordinary individuals. In other words, he is not prescribing indiscriminate harm. He wants rulers to be comfortable with it in limited cases, and economize it.
Secondarily, Machiavelli also agrees that in the medium to long term, it is more important to avoid being hated. After all, the people did outnumber the landed aristocracy so if interests were ever to be misaligned, it is unlikely a ruler could avoid revolution or mass unrest.
Tertiarily, Machiavelli favored a famous animal analogy to explain this idea. He believed that a successful ruler should acquire characteristics exhibited by both a lion and a fox. The lion is the more typical projection of strength and absolute power, being the animal most feared, and as such, is often how we think about Machiavelli’s preference for fear over love. However, Machiavelli also encourages rulers to adopt more foxlike qualities. For instance, while the nobility of princes that always keep their promises is admirable, the more successful princes are ones who cared little for keeping their word and instead learned how to disguise promise-breaking as legitimate. A successful ruler should outwardly represent an image of fear (the lion), despite performing generous and more good-natured actions that would disguise all the duplicitous promise-breaking (the fox).
I want to examine Machiavelli’s theory and its implications vis-a-vis other major philosophical schemes. In the pursuit of an effective principality, is Machiavelli saying “the ends justify the means” or, rather, that to be an effective political leader means doing things that are not fully justifiable? This question, I think, is especially salient because it asks whether Machiavellism requires a certain utilitarian or non-utilitarian moral frame. Let’s use torture as our example. There are practically three schools of thought.
First, you can argue that torture is categorically wrong and should never be practiced.
Second, you can believe that torture is wrong, but sometimes warranted and NOT wrong (or not as wrong) when it is used to achieve good outcomes. For instance, calling back to the text we analyzed in the first installment of Philosophantasy, Peter Singer might argue that torture is wrong as a general principle but torturing suspected terrorists is not wrong for welfare maximization for the greatest number.
Third, is the Machiavellian view. Torture is wrong (as in, we agree that is is the wrong thing), but it sometimes should be done. This belief tracks with Machiavelli’s theory because the responsible leader has to be bad, to a degree. Regardless of whether torture is good or bad, the ruler should be willing to use it.
This distinction vis-a-vis the main utilitarian view of torture is what nuances Machiavelli in a very interesting way. Machiavelli is telling rulers to learn to be able NOT to be good and to use this and not use it according to necessity. Under Machiavelli’s view, there is a relevant difference between being NOT good and NOT being good. He would concede that torture is morally wrong and that its application is immoral, but still argue for its use, whereas the classical utilitarian would say there are particular instances where torture would change from not good to good (if it were utility-maximizing).
Here, I will make a cheeky little appeal to the audience.
If you want a rock-solid example of Machiavellian behavior, look at the book you’re currently reading. In Hamlet, Claudius kills his own brother and uses lying and other forms of manipulation of the people around him to gain power and glory. At the same time, he also disguises his malintent with theatricality and an amenable public image to gain the support of the courtiers and the people around him.
Additionally, note the other motivations and machinations of the characters in Hamlet. Claudius conspires with people to spy on Hamlet and even sends him out of the country. Hamlet focuses on play-acting and convincing everyone that he is mad with grief. The characters Rosencrantz and Guildenstern function strictly as instruments of this deception and duplicity.
Machiavellism is all around us. The world, whether effectual or fictional, contains so many situations and the interplay of interests that come straight from Machiavelli’s manuscript.
“Everyone sees what you appear to be; few experience what you really are.”
Thanks for reading.